print Print
Please select which sections you would like to print:
verifiedCite
While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies. Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.
Select Citation Style
Share
Share to social media
URL
https://mainten.top/science/probability
Feedback
Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login).
Thank you for your feedback

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

In some ways, statistics has finally achieved the Enlightenment aspiration to create a logic of uncertainty. Statistical tools are at work in almost every area of life, including agriculture, business, engineering, medicine, law, regulation, and social policy, as well as in the physical, biological, and social sciences and even in parts of the academic humanities. The replacement of human “computers” with mechanical and then electronic ones in the 20th century greatly lightened the immense burdens of calculation that statistical analysis once required. Statistical tests are used to assess whether observed results, such as increased harvests where fertilizer is applied, or improved earnings where early childhood education is provided, give reasonable assurance of causation, rather than merely random fluctuations. Following World War II, these significance levels virtually came to define an acceptable result in some of the sciences and also in policy applications.

From about 1930 there grew up in Britain and America—and a bit later in other countries—a profession of statisticians, experts in inference, who defined standards of experimentation as well as methods of analysis in many fields. To be sure, statistics in the various disciplines retained a fair degree of specificity. There were also divergent schools of statisticians, who disagreed, often vehemently, on some issues of fundamental importance. Fisher was highly critical of Pearson; Neyman and Egon Pearson, while unsympathetic to father Karl’s methods, disagreed also with Fisher’s. Under the banner of Bayesianism appeared yet another school, which, against its predecessors, emphasized the need for subjective assessments of prior probabilities. The most immoderate ambitions for statistics as the royal road to scientific inference depended on unacknowledged compromises that ignored or dismissed these disputes. Despite them, statistics has thrived as a somewhat heterogeneous but powerful set of tools, methods, and forms of expertise that continues to regulate the acquisition and interpretation of quantitative data.

Theodore M. Porter